ASPECTS
OF VALUE IN CONTEMPORARY PAINTING
Fred T. Martin
(as
published in The College Art Journal, Volume XII, Number 4, Summer 1953, pp
321-328)
IF
THERE is a problem facing contemporary art, it is that we cannot tell the good
from the bad. From this one dilemma come both the shibboleths and genuinely
creative insights of our age. As an example of the former one can take the
constant reiteration of the banality that there is no good or bad and that one
should not speak of "quality"; and as an example of the latter one
could cite the widely held notion, held since Nietzche, that perhaps now if
ever has come the time for the arrival of the new. Few critics now dare to
speak of good painting, though there is much decrying of bad. Rather, most of
them engage in one form or another of "plastic criticism," the
description of colors, lines, etc., and their supposed organization.
Ultimately, questions of good and bad art have been replaced by questions of
the organization or disorganization of the picture plane. However, if we apply
this criterion of organization to painting as it is found in galleries and
studios everywhere, we find that though it separates the ordered from the
disordered it does not always separate the valuable from the worthless.
It
has been the claim of science for many years now that value in science lies in
order. Anthropology analyzes cultures just as a physicist analyzes atoms or
the psychologist minds. All, atoms, minds, and cultures, are found to be
dynamic interrelations of forces whose development in these relations of force
can be predicted with more or less precision. The value of science is felt to
lie in its predictiveness of natural events and in its resultant ability to
control them; and the perception of order which is the basis for
predictiveness is taken as an end value, a value which cannot be reduced to
any other, in itself.
Science
has our age under its thumb, we might as well admit it. All mankind including
the scientists themselves are astounded by its achievements. Since it is so
successful and since we are told that without its help mankind could never
have gone as far as he has (assuming of course that he has gone far), we have
come pretty well to believe that it would be best if we were to apply its
principles to all phases of human activity.
From
the very first stages of modern science‑at least from the Novum Organum‑one
of the cardinal principles has been a belief in the reality of the
mathematical formulation of the universe and a disbelief in the sensuous one.
The worlds of Hobbes and Locke were both based on this, as is today the world
of the atomic physicist. As an example of this disbelief in the sensuous
world, today's atomic physicist, though he has absolutely no direct proof of
the reality of his particles and waves, believes them to belong to an order of
reality far prior to our world of mere colors, lights, mists, and objects. So
the scientific age claims to have been built on the value of a certain kind of
order, a kind of order describing for us a world made purely from objective
elements and utterly divorced from that perceived by our workaday senses. In
art also, as could be expected, such views as these are widely held. Order in
painting is the criterion of value, both with reference to the inherent value
of any given work of art and also in the ascription of originality, where a
novel ordering of supposed more or less objective elements becomes the
archetype of the new.
This
criterion makes possible the contrasting of African with Greek sculpture, of
Chinese Calligraphy with Kandinsky's early non-objective painting, and all of
the other meetings of the arts in our present culture. (There is a scientific
parallel here in the tendency of anthropologists to compare the organization
of various cultures without too much consideration of the content of such
cultures, measuring the "height" of culture by its complexity -- a
criterion of order -- instead of by its content.) We find it easy to
appreciate the art products of the most varied cultures because we have come
to see art as a matter of "style," to use Malraux's term, of form,
instead of a matter of statement, of content. Though we realize that every
form involves something to be formed, we beg the question by claiming that
the degree of forming is the important factor, and that the original substance
which was to be formed is unimportant. In this way we arrive via a scientific
predilection for order and a scientist's disregard for apparent reality at an
unconscious assumption that form can be its own substance.
The
final observation to be made is that good and bad in any age refer only to the
valued and valueless and that consequently in our time good and bad have come
more and more to refer to order and disorder and, in art, to form and its
lack. It will be the purpose of this essay to prove that an error has been
made in assuming as we have that value lies chiefly in order, and an attempt
will be made to show in what other area it may lie. In order to begin, let us
substitute for the usual equivalence of good : bad = ordered : disordered, the
following, i.e., good : bad = valuable : valueless, and let us then follow the
resultant chain of ideas to its final conclusion.
The
first thing we would note is that this second grouping, the one based on value
rather than on order, automatically includes the first, though the first does
not include it. If the number one be added to two, five, and six and the sum
be taken, an organization will have been made. But the organization will have
no value until we learn that it was not one, two, five, and six that we added
but rather that each number was a man (or an orange) and the result was men
(or oranges). The organization will have no value until its content has been
made specific because the value hinges on what the specification may be.
Modern painting and many of the other modern arts have become convinced that
form alone is valuable, that it was the numbers rather than the things that
were counted that were important. Sheldon Cheney, for example, in one of his
older books (Expressionism in Art) seems to believe that the important thing
in painting is `planetary movement'; and, although he captions his chapters
with titles such as Mysticism, The Importance o f Meaning, he yet believes
that planetary movement makes a mystical picture art, not that mysticism makes
a picture with planetary movement art.
To
mention an instance both more common and more recent, it is becoming
apparently more and more widely held among artists (and thus, it is to be
hoped, among critics) that a picture, to be good (of value, liked, or
something) must spread evenly over the whole surface of the picture plane,
that that whole surface must receive equal emphasis, and that there must be no
"void" areas in the picture. This notion seems to guide a great many
if not the most of the younger generation abstract‑expressionist, (the
so-called vanguard) painters, though it seem nearly totally absent among the
elder practitioners of this school. What is to be noted here is not so much
the "form" itself as that for which it stands; for, notwithstanding
their form, or perhaps, even in spite of it, we must determine whether these
pictures have any value beyond form. Have they any value based in the original
substance from which they are shaped, or from some other, as yet unanalyzed
source, or, perhaps, have they no values at all except formal ones?
It
is certainly true that these paintings do have value for the person who paints
them, even if he will not tell us in what that value lies other than form; for
he keeps them, wants to show them, and oft‑times sacrifices some
personal gain for them. However, we must decide if they have any other values,
ones somehow intrinsic. We must discover if they have values for any other use
than to tell (by way of their formal type) to their creator that he is an
artist, a member of that brotherhood and so with some claim to regard over and
above what every one else gets or fails to get.
Actually,
a terribly vital problem is centered here. It is simply the old question, Who
are we? Have we any value, any use over and above our function as producer and
consumer? There is probably only one institution in the history of man which
has been regularly charged with answering this question, with supplying man
with the ecstasy, the going beyond himself, the conviction of transcendent
purpose or value, necessary for life. This institution is of course religion.
Many people today think that religion, at least in the west, is dying. Others
claim the reverse. But, for either to have such notions shows that for them
the possibility exists that at least it may die. If it may die, its ecstatic
function may be eclipsed. But this function must be absolute, for to doubt for
an instant that man is more than an animal or a machine is to doubt it
forever. Therefore, for many people religion can be said to be dead, at least
in this function. However, though man may be only a buyer of brands, though
there be no holy church to confer on him his godhead, might there riot be some
race apart, some race of men more than men‑a race of artists? To belong
to this group, then, would be to live again, to know the ecstasy without which
life is worthless.
Why
not go back to the young painter (most of the old ones who have recently
changed their style are the same) and take another look at him? Is he finding
in painting merely a substitute for religion‑ in other words, is art his
claim to being different, to being important for himself and not merely as a
brand buyer or builder of Hooper Ratings? I believe that frequently this is
exactly the case, that art is his claim to "being," that it is his
ecstasy. Back then to our original problem: Why are his works valuable, first
of all, to him? They are valuable as signs that he is of the elect, and they
mean to him that he is different, an individual, worthwhile in and for himself
at least in so far as he is an artist. Have they any value for us, since they
don't prove us to be members of some holy band? None that I can see, unless we
join the small devoted group of appreciators without which the holy band would
die.
Why
must they be vanguard works by the way? Because in the making of vanguard
works the value, the affirmation of one's own important existence, is
greatest; for everyone in the vanguard knows that he is "making reality
for tomorrow" (for yesterday's and today's are dead). Besides, the
vanguard is attacked from all sides and one feels a martyr for it just as one
feels for one's own soul in the present day world. And as a last inducement to
join the avant‑guard there is the fact which everyone knows: that the
modern world is built on progress and that art is not different from
refrigerator making in this: that every year it gets better and better. And so
the value of his paintings lies not in the original substance from which they
were built but is rather an expression of his personal relation to them. They
are expressions of his faith that salvation shall come to him because he is a
vanguard painter and that only as such will his life have value. The works
have no intrinsic value to him; their only value is as proof that he is a
member of the elect. But, even though his works have value to him only as
badges to show his membership, might they not have some value to us as
revelations of a new reality, since this revelation is the avowed function of
the vanguard of which he is a member?
Well,
then, what is the nature of this vanguard, the nature of its aims, and its
sources? Does its works reveal a new reality? To take the questions one at a
time, the concept of vanguard arises of course from the fact that some artists
consciously believe that they have an historical purpose, a purpose which is
generally described by aestheticians as "the integration of new materials
(forms, techniques, and subjects) into the tradition." The artists
themselves generally take a more dramatic view of their aims and believe,
especially today, that they are creating a whole new tradition. The idea of a
vanguard first became popular in the late nineteenth century, though the seeds
of it are certainly present back at least as far as David, who made probably
the first conscious modification in the tradition of western painting.
Vanguard means, really, those who are on the fore front, those painters who
see into the haze of tomorrow and paint its painting today. Their origin lies,
then, in a concept of history and of inevitable progress in art; their aims
are to heal the consciously felt wounds of their age.
But
does vanguard‑ness automatically mean value in art? The vanguard artist
bases his claim to value on a theory of history and progress in art. He
assumes somehow that every true vanguard artist down through the ages has
stood on the shoulders of the man who went before him, that the generations
stand pyramided reaching toward heaven and that he is at the top. He would, of
course, be the first to admit that many of the pyramids have been built inside
out or upside down (the Impressionist or Nabis for example), but he would
insist that his at least is built on true lines.
In
science each man builds on what each other man does, science too is such a
vanguard pyramid. There is a conceptual framework holding the whole structure
together, and each man's task is to illuminate a facet of the entire building,
showing either how even in this spot the formula for the entire building holds
true, or else that relations are such here as to call into question the entire
formula as held until now and to suggest consequent modifications.
Every
scientist works with the symbols of every other, and this very fact of the
precise communicability of symbols proves to the scientist their truth --
unless B gets exactly the same experimental results as A and is able to draw
exactly the same conclusions, the whole experiment is suspect. There are then
three earmarks of scientific pursuit. The first is universal applicability of
laws, the second is the universal validity of mathematical formulation, and
the third, the result of the first two, is the usefulness of and the necessity
for universal exchange of information to the end that each scientist may add
his appropriate piece to the whole. If we were to look for an historical term
which could sum all this up, we would say that it is "progress," the
continual growing and enriching in time of a continuing organism. It is for
this reason that observations, conclusions, etc. made a hundred years ago have
now only an historical, not a vital, interest for us. The organism of science
has grown beyond them, and has robbed them of their aspect of vital truth,
leaving them only the historical interest connected with any stepping stone.
The
vanguard artist in most cases subscribes to this view of science, but he
applies it to art as well. He makes this application in these ways: He usually
believes that the art of the past is of purely historical interest, and that
it commits errors as foolish as believing the sun revolves around the earth.
He thinks that each artist of the vanguard must build on the work "the
discoveries" of each other. He believes that these
"discoveries" are embodied in a freely communicable, precisely
interpretable language, a language as flexible as mathematics, where the
formulas and the discoveries of an Einstein can be applied to astronomy or
atomic physics. He therefore believes that it is necessary to know exactly
"what they're doing in New York" because that is believed by him to
be the center or artistic discovery, just as a scientist might be interested
in knowing what is being done at an Institute for Advanced Studies. He even
has his Einstein in the person of Hans Hoffman or some other artist who is
supposed to be in the very forefront of discovery. All of this forms a
coherent, well organized body of thought as well as action, and for this
reason if no other, if value lies in form, it is probable that these
conceptions are valuable and that the vanguard artist is doing valuable work.
But
should it be that value lies not in form but is perhaps the sperm of chaos,
then far other will be our view of artists' lives, and our attribution of
their worth. Suppose we assume then (merely for the sake of argument, if only
for a reduction ad absurdam) that value lies not in the net of form cast over
chaos but rather that it lies somewhere in that very chaos itself. Perhaps it
may even lie throughout chaos, dwelling immanently there like some have said
God does in the world. Then the aspect of a picture which has value will not
be its form but will instead be the primitive substance which was formed and
which is now frozen somehow forever in that picture's net of art.
To
begin to hunt the lair of value in the land of chaos (if it be there at all)
we might analyze the very objectness of an object. It is a thing separated
from things, and it is present. Insofar as it is present it has no past or
future, nor can it have such, for the very conception of presentness is a
contradiction of past and future. Just so, too, if the thing be lighted in
this present; for then dark will have been annihilated forever, relegated to
the place whence past and future have fled. In this way are all things (both
the primitive substances of things and their modifying attributes) made naught
by the existence of this one. But, by their very separateness from this object
of our attention, they make it teal; for, without their tyranny of nothingness
beating upon the shores of our object, we would never have that object.
Day
cannot be without night to break against its cliffs, nor can present be found
but by looking to the hems of past and future. Thus, thingness pre-supposes
and demands nothingness to make it real, and form must have unform before ever
it can be. Can value be found only in some cranny of this world of unform, of
nothing, or must it be (if it be here at all) present throughout, immanent
like God may be in the world? The place where all those things dwell which are
not now (the mansions of the past and of the future, the houses of night and
of death) is the place of nothing, and by that very word out question is
answered. If it is the place of nothing, then all those things which have been
lost in its deeps (and value too if it dwelleth there) are one, indivisibly
and eternally; for each one of them is nothing, and nothing knows no
distinction of this or that. This and that when dwelling in nothing are each
immanent in the other, and so they dwell there in one another simultaneously
in an eternity frozen into matter.
This,
then, is what matter is. It is the unknowable substance beneath the threshold
of mind, it is the stuff of things whose forms only we can know, it is the
unform, the nothing, behind every form in our experience. Might value lie
there, in this hidden place? If it be not present in form then it must be
caught in the deeps of matter‑it must be not only caught but also must
be the very substance of matter, for all those who dwelleth there dwelleth as
one, and each is the other for all eternity.
Was
value found in form -- can we tell the good from the bad in art today? Form
can be used as a criterion in the discussion of art. But can it tell us which
picture has an intrinsic value, some value over and above mere membership in a
school? We have searched, and found no certain proof that it can. Then, if
value perhaps be not caught in form, there is only one other place to look and
that is in the deeps of chaos, deeps where all are one, where, if value be at
all, value is everywhere. Then value would be in the matter of pictures, it
would be in the nothing of their thingness, in the unform of their form.
Therefore that picture which is valued for its form might be valueless, and
only that work -- or that man -- who is valuable for some un-nameable quality
beneath form would be of worth.